Against Theological Fatalism
CRITICS OF
THEISM, along with some theists, often claim that divine foreknowledge
contradicts human free will. “Since God already knew what actions you were
going to take,” they argue, “it follows necessarily that you had no choice but
to take those same actions.” Basically, the argument for theological fatalism
holds God’s knowledge to be the ultimate causal agent of all future outcomes,
hence the ultimate metaphysical outworking of the pragmatic principle that
“knowledge is power.” It is my belief that properly understood, knowledge
comprehends true states of affairs, but does not and cannot create them. (To
put it another way: Even if God personally dictated our future, he would have
to do so by means other than mere knowledge of our future.) There is accordingly
no sound reason to believe that God’s prior knowledge of human decisions freely
rendered should not represent a true state of affairs.
At stake
here is much more than academic philosophy or theology. For Christian theists
the issue of fatalism lies at the heart of our faith, for if the God we believe
in is righteous, he will presumably only hold us accountable for decisions we
make. As Davis and Manis state the problem, "If divine foreknowledge
undermines human freedom, then it seems to follow that God is unjust in holding
us responsible for our actions."[1] Somewhat like the argument from evil, the
argument for fatalism seems designed to get humans "off the hook" for
our behavior and to put God on the hook instead.
Zagzebski
describes theological fatalism as "the thesis that infallible
foreknowledge of a human act makes the act necessary and hence unfree. If there
is a being who knows the entire future infallibly, then no human act is
free."[2] There is certainly some intuitive appeal to this claim. Indeed,
at a glance it appears obvious, if not entirely beyond dispute. Davis and Manis
suggest, for example, that if God knew from all eternity past that Smith will
call his wife tomorrow at noon then clearly Smith has no choice but to make
that call. "God's foreknowledge is infallible — it cannot possibly be
mistaken — so there is no chance that Smith will falsify God's past beliefs
about him when he acts tomorrow."[3]
My
contention is that this appeal to the necessary "rightness" of God's
foreknowledge of events blurs the distinction between
metaphysical causality and logical entailment. It is admittedly logically necessary that if God has
perfect foreknowledge, he knows the outcomes of all future decisions. But the question
is: Does God's knowledge determine the outcome, or is the outcome instead a
passive source of God's knowledge? Experience suggests the latter. After all, I
know that you are reading this right now, but I also know that I did not prevent you from doing something else instead.
Consider the following set of scenarios:
Consider the following set of scenarios:
1. At 8:15
Harold will be free to order anything on the menu.
2. God has
infallible foreknowledge.
3. God
infallibly foreknew that at 8:15 Harold would be free to order anything on the
menu.
This first
scenario suggests that God's perfect foreknowledge does not necessarily
restrict free will, at least not with respect to Harold's capacity to ponder a
decision not yet made. In other words, it's a possible scenario. After all, the
argument from fatalism specifically says that God's prior knowledge of a choice
actually made must negate the free will to make any other choice. But on that
argument there is no reason to think that free will should not be operative before any choice has actually been made.
That is, even under the premises of fatalism foreknowledge does not negate free
will to at least deliberate, i.e., to think over a choice. What then of God's
prior knowledge of Harold's actualized decisions? Let's fast-forward fifteen
minutes:
1. At 8:30
Harold will order a cheese omelet.[4]
2. God has
infallible foreknowledge.
3. God
infallibly foreknew that at 8:30 Harold would order a cheese omelet.
Again we
have a possible scenario. But now the question presents itself, whether the
free will Harold potentially enjoyed in the first scenario might have remained
operative through the point of making a decision in scenario two. From scenario
one it seems at least arguable that Harold will be free to order anything from
the menu, but (arguably) only up to the point at which he will have already
ordered a cheese omelet. Free will after that point admittedly will have been
forfeited with respect to that particular decision. So:
1. At 8:31
Harold will no longer be free to not order a cheese omelet, because he will
have already ordered one.
2. God has
infallible foreknowledge.
3. God
infallibly foreknew that at 8:31 Harold would no longer be free to not order a cheese omelet, having already ordered one.
Free will
with respect to Harold's decision thus becomes forfeited just at the point of
Harold's having already made that decision. (This is not to say he can't "change his mind," call the waiter over and order something different, only that he has in fact ordered it. It's a very small part of human history at this point.) On the face of it, though, there is
nothing in the forfeiture of Harold's free will with respect to a decision
already made that would additionally preclude his free will prior to making the
decision. All this would seem to yield the general conclusion: God's
foreknowledge does not necessarily contradict human free will. Or alternatively:
Theological fatalism is false. Once
due attention is paid to the respective definitions and functions of free will
and omniscience, the two are seen to be in harmony. Free will remains
unrestricted in making decisions which result in unchangeable outcomes, and
divine foreknowledge remains infallibly knowledgeable of everything knowable.
In Harold's case what negates his freedom to not order a cheese omelet is
precisely his prior act of having freely ordered one. There is no contradiction
here, only a description of two states of being at two different times relative
to the decison made. As Zagzebski suggests, “The necessity of the past and the
contingency of the future are two sides of the same coin.”[5]
The curious
part about all this is God's knowledge of human freedom to make a decision
whose outcome God alone knows in advance. But in principle human freedom is a
knowable state, and God’s knowledge necessarily corresponds exactly with any
given knowable state. In the state of human free will prior to a decision event
the decision outcome is less than certain for a human decider; God’s knowledge
of that state remains certain, as does his knowledge of the future state of
more restricted freedom created by the decision outcome. God’s knowledge of both
states does not make his knowledge contradictory, but complete and
comprehensive. This is precisely the sort of knowledge an omniscient God would
be expected to have.
Again, the
question is not whether a choice, once made, results in an outcome which cannot
be changed. Decisions result in certain outcomes, quite regardless of whether
an omniscient being exists or not. The question is whether a choice whose
certain outcome also happens to be known by an all-knowing entity could have
been freely made. There is no a priori reason to think that knowledge of
another's behavior determines that behavior; the behavior, rather, is the
source of the knowledge. So, an external agent’s prior knowledge would have no
bearing upon the fact that decisions already made are unchangeable. To see that
this is so, let’s revisit our breakfast with Harold and this time assume there
is no God:
1. There is
no God.
2. At 8:15
Harold will be free to order anything on the menu.
3. At 8:30
Harold will order a cheese omelet.
4. At 8:31
Harold will no longer be free to not order a cheese omelet, because he will
have already ordered one.
Even with no
God in existence, Harold remains just as free to order a cheese omelet at 8:15,
and just as unable to not have already ordered one at 8:31. Harold's inability
to not have already ordered one has, in a sense, been predetermined — not by
God, who in this scenario does not exist — but by Harold's prior decision.
Therefore whether God exists or not, every possible future is “predetermined”
and free will does not operate, at least not with respect to prior decisions.
Nonetheless, it remains logically possible that we are free to make decisions
up to the point that we actually make them, just as we will be free to make new
decisions in the future.
Now let’s
add an omniscient God back into the mix. God knows with absolute certainty or
perfect knowledge that Harold will order a cheese omelet at 8:30, and that
afterward he cannot choose to have done otherwise. But how exactly does the additional
fact of God knowing exactly what Harold will decide entail a necessary
violation of Harold's free will in actually making the decision? We have just
seen that without God’s or anyone else’s knowledge of it, Harold's inability to
not have already ordered a cheese omelet after ordering one would be just as
certain. God’s knowledge of the future, then, would not make it any more
certain than it would be without his knowledge.
If it is the
case that a decision event involves free will in the consideration of choices
at some given point in time, resulting in an irreversible outcome that holds at
all points future to it, then in principle an omniscient being knowledgeable of
all points along the timeline of all events would know not only of the element
of free will inherent in the process of making decisions, but of the
unchangeable outcomes that result from those decisions. There would be nothing
contradictory or illogical in this.
_____________
[1] C.
Stephen Davis and R. Zachary Manis, Philosophy of Religion. 2nd ed. Downer's
Grove, Illinois: Intervarsity, p. 45.
[2] Linda
Zagzebski, ed. E.N. Zalta,
“Foreknowledge and Free Will,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
2011, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/free-will-foreknowledge/.
[3] Davis
and Manis, Philosophy of Religion, p. 45.
[4] After completing
this article including references to my real-life friend Harold, who really does enjoy
cheese omelets for breakfast, I did a quick search for "theological
fatalism" and came across a blog posting responding to an argument for
fatalism by William Hasker. It turns out that in Hasker's version, the first
premise is "It is now true that Clarence will have a cheese omelet for
breakfast tomorrow (Premise)," and goes on from there. See
http://ochuk.wordpress.com/2012/02/16/a-response-to-theological-fatalism/. The
common "cheese omelet" element in my argument and Hasker's is purely
coincidental... unless of course God preordained it.
[5]
Zagzebski, "Foreknowledge and Free Will."
Comments
Or you are prophetic. or great minds think alike ;-)
great article Don. That is the view I hold theone you expressed, well argued. I have had that argument on many message boards. one o the great philosophical classics of the church is by Boetheius, Consolation of Philosophy. Foreknowledge does not equal (//=)Predestination.
I don't deserve that compliment, but I'll happily take it anyway. :-)
Actually that essay is a modified version of an argument I presented years ago at the old FRDB discussion board. During that lively discussion Wayne Delia (an exceptionally bright atheist, in my opinion) had appealed to his own formal argument for fatalism, which led me to write this rebuttal.
that's what Laplace thought. Only he was an atheist so it wasn't God in control but determinism. MANY ATHEISTS ARE STILL DETERMINISTS. why does it have to mean that God really guide evolution to us? Why couldn't it he just let it produce whomever it produces?